There
is a moment in Meillassoux's After Finitude
that threatens to subvert his entire argument. This moment comes towards the
end of the book, in the chapter ‘Ptolemy's Revenge’:
‘The world of Cartesian extension is a world that acquires the independence of substance, a world that we can henceforth conceive of as indifferent to everything in it, that corresponds to the concrete, organic connection that we forge with it – it is the glacial world that is revealed to the moderns, a world in which there is no longer any up or down, centre or periphery, nor anything else that might make of it a world designed for humans. For the first time, the world manifests itself as capable of subsisting without any of those aspects that constitute its concreteness for us’ (115).
The
modern world is a ‘glacial’ one, one which presents no clear will of a god or
saviour, and simultaneously presents a scientific system that disavows common
perception, that refutes common perception of the world. Here the moderns are
presumably the post-Enlightenment thinkers, which include Schelling, Burke and
others who have theorised not the real directly, but apprehensions of the real
couched in phenomenology. Despite the 'correlationism' that these thinkers may
be subject to, they have certainly felt the exposure of this glacial world that
became manifest in their modern world. This ‘glacial world’ of the moderns
presents ample opportunity for drama, an opportunity that is almost entirely
avoided in Meillassoux's stark proof, until we hit the very incongruous remark.
This remark is distinctive and significant because it crystallises a notable
absence from Meillassoux's theory: the absence of a link between sensation and
the real: what is the experience of realism? And, if knowledge that exceeds
human life or presence is possible as Meillassoux argues, how is this connected
or disconnected from sense? What is even more striking about Meillassoux's
remark, in addition to the departure from the overall style of Meillassoux's
text, is that it echoes so closely Burke's key illustration of the experience
of the sublime. In this post I'd like to articulate how it becomes possible for
Meillassoux to argue for a realism that excludes mediation and attraction, and
to replace these bridges with an understanding of knowledge of that which
subtracts from experience. Here, I will also attempt to draw a distinction
between Graham Harman's concept of allure, which is a form of attraction to
hidden depths of receding objects as well as a form of articulating realism,
which still retains a primacy of sensation that Meillassoux does away with. One
of the hardest aspects of Meillassoux's text is the absence of any clear
theories of either attraction to the real, or mediation between consciousness
and the real. This is, in the first instance, not because he rejects outright a
role for either of these theoretical components. Meillassoux has gone on, after
the publication of After Finitude, to publish on mathematical writing, and its distinction
from natural language, which certainly addresses the latter category that I am
presenting here, mediation. This work is found in Meillassoux's essay
'Contingence et Absolutisation de l'Un', a paper which was presented at the
Sorbonne conference on ‘Métaphysique, Ontologie, Hénologie.’
Here
I merely want to show how speculative materialism necessarily goes beyond
theories that incorporate negative sensation, leaving a necessary void where
sensation should be: this is not an articulable sense, but a subtraction from
sense, as impossible as such a thing may seem. This subtraction from sense is most importantly achieved
through transitive and / or transfinite deductions, which do not pursue depths
or chains of objects, but rather performs a diagonal cut in the form of the
mathematical proof.
Negative
Sensation and the Psychoanalytic Real
It
seems incomprehensible that there should be a theory of materialism that
excludes sensation; even theories of the real, it seems, should include some
kind of sensation, and usually they do: here I am thinking of the infinity that
Schelling finds within and Burke's concept of the sublime, in addition to
Lacan’s concept of fantasy and Harman’ concept of allure. The presumed
necessity of sensation often rests on another, unspecific psychoanalytic
assumption about human knowledge: that in every act, every pursuit of
knowledge, something must be gained (even if, hypothetically, this knowledge is
one that exceeds human life). This (still vaguely) psychoanalytic scepticism
presumes that the impulse towards a philosophical realism must afford something
to the subject that pursues this, i.e. that the pursuit of the real is in some
ways an aspect of the pleasure principle. This is, in a way, a first objection
to Meillassoux's speculative materialism that proceeds from the grounds of
sensation, but is interesting because it proceeds from the grounds of negative
sensation and negative reason: an intention that the subject obscures from
itself. This provides an (admittedly crude) refutation that at once
reintegrates speculative realism back into correlationism, but not into any
simple binding of perception by phenomenology, rather into subjective or
unconscious, and hence even more isolated, fulfilment. Alenka Zupančič gives the
sophisticated version of this objection in her lecture at the European Graduate
School entitled 'The Fantasy of Speculative Realism', avoiding the easy
reintegration of the realist position into correlationism whilst also
addressing the psychoanalytic understanding of the real. Zupančič claims that
in Meillassoux we see a ‘complicity’ with the ‘fantasy of the great outdoors,
which will save us’ and that this fantasy is a ‘screen that covers up the fact
that discursive reality is itself leaking, contradictory, and entangled with
the real as its irreducible other side’.
Here
the attraction to the real comes not in the form of the sublime or other
extreme emotional state, but in the form of a pure saviour that would justify
or make sense of (what is for Lacan a) discursive reality. This objection to
Meillassoux is made not on the basis of intuition or phenomenon, but rather
fantasy, which is at once absolutely subjective yet at the same time does not
take the form of a straightforward or positive sensation. Zupančič will counter
Meillassoux with Lacan's conviction that modern science creates the real;
nature is unchanged by physics, and unaffected by discourse (and that is why,
following Lacan, she remarks somewhat wryly that we love nature so much).
Zupančič will go on to illustrate Lacan's positions on science and his own
identification as a dialectical materialist. For Lacan, the epistemic and
semiotic relation to the real is necessarily a mute one: we can say nothing
about immanent reality, it simply is as it is. This is where Lacan and
Meillassoux may agree: the depths that empiricism attempts to reach are
ultimately futile. If we want to produce facts about nature, this is a separate
reality, Lacan would contest; empiricism does not access depths so much as make
a new cut into reality (and in this he is quite distinct from Meillassoux).
Here Lacan by no means inoculates the real that science creates, for indeed he
acknowledges that the scientific cut is powerful, because it has effects on in
the real, the example here being the arrival of a man on the moon. Nature – the
moon – however will be unchanged by this. The ‘reduction to the letter’ that
science makes is a process of a ‘cut’ and a ‘substitution’; the scientific
letter does not replace anything, it substitutes for something. This for Lacan
is the ‘link between discursivity and the real’, hence resulting in a
dialectical stance. For Meillassoux, however, the mathematisation of primary
qualities shows what of the object exists without the human. For Lacan, this is
quite different, because this mathematisation has consequences in terms of
constructing a new piece of the real, without affecting nature in the least. It
is this unaffected nature which is, for Lacan, the real. Here Lacan uses a
metaphor of the net to illustrate what he is describing: the language or marks
of empiricism are the net, and the real is precisely what does not fall through
such a net. Here, I take the net to be both a sieve of interpretation, but also
the form of the cut in the real: one might think of the net billowing in the
winds of the real, formed by these conditions but not articulating them. In
this sense, Lacan’s ‘net’ is a mediating device between human science and the
real, even if it does not articulate or describe the real per se, because the device still takes on a form, makes a
cut in the real, and has effects. Simultaneously, the net is also a barrier
between human knowledge and the real, without this being easily collapsed into
a correlationist position. If we transport the metaphor of the net to
Meillassoux, we might say that speculative materialism takes the net to ‘stick’
to the real, to represent and enact primary qualities. In both of these cases,
we result in speculative methodologies: things can be entirely other than their
present state, and in both cases science touches the real, but in Meillassoux
this becomes knowledge – this absolute is ‘absolutely thinkable’, whereas for
Lacan this is exactly that which is always precluded from knowledge. For Lacan
the idea that the form of the net will fall in form of the real is a grave
misapprehension, specifically a misapprehension that confuses the fantasy of an
absolute with knowledge. The difference here is the same difference that Graham
Harman isolates between his own philosophy and Meillassoux’s: Lacan moves from
a position of weak correlationism, and radicalises it, whereas Meillassoux
departs form a position of ‘strong correlationism’ (which is not to bring Lacan
and Harman into agreement at all; their concepts of the real and knowledge
could not be more different). The only similarity here is that weak
correlationism incorporates a philosophy of attraction whilst simultaneously
articulating a speculative position, whereas a radicalisation of the strong
correlationist position does not. I’ll now turn to looking at Harman’s
theoretical articulations of attraction and mediation devices in relation to
realism, to consider an alternative to fantasy as attraction device.
Negative
Sensation and Object-Oriented Ontology
The
concept of ‘allure’ is Harman’s key formulation of an attraction to the real.
Allure is the articulation of the sense of depths of the object: although for
Harman we do not have access to the object in its real existence, and the
object necessarily withdraws from human perception, we do have a sense of those
depths that move away from us. In this sense, the concept of allure manages to
capture a contradiction: both a proximity, a closeness to the object, and a
withdrawal of the object. The term allure also, of course, refers to the way in
which we would refer to such objects: not through direct reference, but through
allusion. Allure is not the identity of the object, but is rather a force
between things and humans: ‘sincerity occurs everywhere in the universe at all
times, since a thing always just is what it is; allure is a special and
intermittent experience in which the intimate bond between a thing's unity and
its plurality of notes somehow partially disintegrates. This is an important
point that will require further development. But clearly it is just the sort of
thing we are looking for: the entire method of this book hinges on drawing up a
geographic atlas of the bonds and joints between the four poles of being,
mapping their union and dissolution’ (Guerrilla Metaphysics, 143). In his own 'Manifesto for Object-Oriented
Philosophy' Levi Bryant insists that any theory of the real needs to include a
theory of langue, a system that occupies the space between the world and
consciousness, and this does seem necessary to account for the tendency of
speculative realisms to appeal to the sublime, the glacial, the real, the other
side or the great outdoors: all, at least since Burke, concepts loaded with
affective import. Harman's version of langue is the forces of attraction – the
allure – that operates between the mind, drawing it towards the withdrawing
object. What is striking about Harman’s version of object oriented philosophy,
and specifically about this concept of allure, is the distinction between
objects and forces, which seems peculiarly human. Of course, Harman addresses
this through his concept of tool-being, using that initial human perception,
impulse or relation to the world as a stepping stone in order to comprehend
some form of access to the real. This form of attraction is itself based in
sense and by no means exceeds human finitude (for Harman, this is not a problem
because objects are finite anyway, and knowledge of objects is thus
manufactures only ever within relation).
But the object-force distinction, like causality, is not necessary, and
remains only a theory of sensory relation to objects rather than any rigorous
concept of the real, even if that real is excluded from human knowledge, even
if that absolute is unthinkable. What is strong about Harman's philosophy, and
deeply appealing, is precisely this stepping stone approach, which is somewhat
lacking in After Finitude: the theorisation of a mediation and attraction
device that is rooted in sensation, and explains a non-subjective impetus for
pursuit of objects, of knowledge. But what is disappointing is the
reappropriation of the real into an economy of finitude: effectively
reintegrating the universe into an economy of finite relations of allure: there
is both no absolute, and also no apprehension of existence that exceeds our
relation to objects, or that exceeds, importantly, belief. This concept of
allure might indeed be the element of Harman's philosophy that aligns him with
a tradition of German idealism, as well as the aesthetic and metaphysical
theories of Edmund Burke. This affiliation seems closest in Schelling's
writings on the infinite. For Schelling, for instance, the attraction of
realism is in part because of recognition, the recognition of something in
ourselves: ‘When the series is obliterated, nothing remains except the feeling
of an infinite tendency in our- selves—this tendency now emerges in intuition,
and the above expression of the poet should be considered in this regard. From
this it becomes clear that originally all infinity lies in ourselves’ (First Outline of a System of
Philosophy of Nature, 15). For both Schelling and Harman, the
infinite, the real beyond human grasp, is sensed, through different forms of
intuition, and notably both philosophers then have a particularly stake in
aesthetics and art as exemplary of this tendency. This intuition of that which
goes beyond us constitutes a kind of negative sensation, a sense of the beyond,
in these philosophies, a sense that is notably excluded in Meillassoux, except
for the one, rogue comment about the glacial.
I
have very briefly skimmed through three different forms of negative sensation
that provide a theory of langue, or in my words theoretical devices of
mediation and attraction, for theories of realism (or, in Schelling's case,
necessary for an engagement with the infinite). These elements of a theory seem
necessary for any metaphysical theory, if only because it seems impossible to
have knowledge that is exempted from some sort of sensation. Without wanting to
collapse various theories of the knowledge and the real into one another, the
common way to deal with the necessity of an intuitive or experiential relation
to the real that precludes or anticipates knowledge is through theories of
negative sensation. Meillassoux's work is devoid of any theory of mediation and
attraction, or of the concepts of negative sensation that may be associated
with this. Harman claims that ‘even
for some readers who admire Meillassoux’s verve, his proofs sometimes have the
flavor of St Anselm’s ontological argument, in which the agility of the mind
outruns genuine belief’ (Harman, Quentin Meillassoux: Philosophy in
the Making, 124) On one level the remark
about belief is an apt description of the experience of reading Meillassoux or
relating his ideas to others, but I also think that this claim of Harman’s
fundamentally misses the point. Meillassoux is attempting to argue for the
possibility of thought beyond human existence and thus belief is somewhat
irrelevant here. One does not, for instance, have to believe in mathematical
formulas that exceed intuitive or imaginative availability. For
Meillassoux, belief, and certainly subjective suggestion, of knowledge that
exceeds human intuition or sensation, are unnecessary and even contradictory to
knowledge of the real, where the real is that which exceeds human life; primary qualities do not simply exceed or go beyond the
subject (as if the subject would be retained as a starting point), they are
independent of it. What Meillassoux is pointing to here is necessarily that
which exempts itself from intuition or affect: he goes beyond negative
sensation to look at exactly that which subtracts itself from sensation. The
prime example here is found in the transfinite mode of counting, which is easily
illustrated in the mathematical paradoxes that caused problems for early 20th
century set theory. Whilst Russell's paradox is the best known of all of these,
another paradox illustrates the impossibility of completing a set using naïve
set theory. The briefest and clearest example here is a sort of linguistic
trick that is used by Lacan in ‘Seminar 14: The Logic of Phantasy’. In one of
his seminars, Lacan writes the following on the blackboard:
1 2 3 4
the smallest whole number which is not written on this
board
The
initial answer to this might seem to be the number five. However, it quickly
becomes clear that the number five thereby is written on the board and thereby we have to default over to answering with the number six,
and then seven, and so on. Even if the number five, and six, and so on are not
immediately part of the set of the first line of numbers, they are referred to
through a different form of signification in the second line, a signifying
chain that does not stop: one starts from five and must keep going in order to
answer the sentence. This little trick is effectively a representation of
transitive set. Obviously one comes to the conclusion, eventually, that the
numbers do not stop: you would have to proceed to five, and then to six, and then
to seven, and onwards and onwards: but, crucially, you do not have to go on
counting forever, rather one can see that, in principle, there is an act of
repetition with minimal difference that goes on and on. This realisation comes
from an apprehension of the numbers subtracting, rather than adding, in front
of one. Even if one deployed ordinal or cardinal numbers to try to complete the
problem, one would end up with the same effect (eventually one could just cry
'ω'! and be done with the problem). One has no subjective sense of these
numbers: only of the principle of constant movement, constant repetition that
always creates difference. It is this same effect that Meillassoux is dealing
with, and this is why, going back to Harman's impression, his arguments may
seem like St Anselm's ontological argument: very hard to believe. But this is
precisely because the transfinite knowledge that he is in part working with to
develop his theory of contingency and advent excludes belief; just as the
little game of Lacan's does not require that you believe the numbers will keep
going on: you simply know this. Similarly, you do not need any sense, positive
or negative, of the number chain, or the infinity of natural numbers that is
represented by ω. What this is, rather, is a system that exceeds one and
excludes one, and this is known not by a continuity of numbers but of the
transitive principle of the thing: a diagonal rather than linear form of count
that, after the initial few numerical lunges, operates on the basis of
principle, a principle that makes a cut across the procedure or experience of
counting.
This is how Meillassoux constructs a theory of the real
that does not require belief or attraction, and why he does not theorise
mediation devices. Although the example here uses writing in the first
instance, the transitive principle is represented only by mathematical symbols.
This is the fine line that he cuts between knowledge without belief, and an
absolute without sensation.
Baylee Brits, Sydney, 2013
Bryant, Levi. ‘Onticology: A Manifesto
for Object Oriented Ontology.’ Larval Subjects. [http://larvalsubjects.wordpress.com/2010/01/12/object-oriented-ontology-a-manifesto-part-i/]
Harman, Graham. Guerrilla Metaphysics:
Phenomenology and the Carpentry of Things. Chicago: Open Court, 2005.
-------. Quentin Meillassoux: Philosophy in the Making. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University
Press, 2011.
Schelling, F. W. J. First Outline of a System of
Philosophy of Nature. trans. Keith R. Peterson. Albany: State University of New York Press,
2004.
Zupančič, Alenka. ‘The Fantasy of
Speculative Realism’. European Graduate School: Saas-Fe, Switzerland. 2011.
Lecture.
http://anthem-group.net/2013/07/12/john-caputo-on-speculative-realisms-latour-zizek-and-more/
ReplyDelete-dmf